Title: Lecture 5 Consumer Choice under uncertainty
1Lecture 5Consumer Choice under uncertainty
- Simple lottery
- A simple lottery L is a list L(p1pn) with pn?0
for all n and , where pn is the probability of
the outcome n occurring - We can define more complex lotteries (lotteries
over lotteries) - Compound lottery
- Given k simple lottery , k1K and some
probability that that a lottery Lk occurs, then
we can define a compound lottery , which is the
risky alternative that give Lk with probability
2Lotteries
- Example
- Prize100
- Compound lottery A
- L1(100,0,0) occurs with probability 1/3
- L2(1001/4, 100 3/8, 1003/8) with probability
1/3 - L3((1001/4, 1003/8, 1003/8) with probability
1/3 - Compound lottery B
- L1(1001/2, 1001/2, 0) with probability ½
- L2(1001/2, 0, 1001/2) with probability ½
- Do you prefer A or B?
3Reduced Lotteries
4Reduced lotteries
- Given all the possible outcomes, we can apply the
same logic to compute the probability of each
outcome and hence find the Reduced Lottery
5Reduced lotteries
6Preference over compound lotteries
- Since the consumer only cares about the
distribution of final outcomes, he will be
indifferent between to Compound Lotteries that
deliver the same Reduced Lottery - Do you agree?
7Preferences over lotteries
- Remember when we defined preferences over a set
of goods. - Again now we have to define preferences but over
a space of lotteries - AXIOMS - We require
- Continuity - given two lotteries, small changes
in probabilities do not change the ordering
between two lotteries - Indipendence if we mix each of the two lotteries
with a third one, the preference ordering of the
two resulting mixtures does not depend on the
particular third lottery that is used. - Note the difference with the consumer choice
under certainty here when we consider three
alternative lotteries L1, L2 and L3, the consumer
cannot consumer L1 and L2 together or L1 and L3
together etc. but he has to choose between
mutually exclusive alternatives!
8Expected Utility
9Expected Utility
- Expected Utility theorem
- If preferences over lotteries satisfy the
continuity and the independence axioms, then
preferences can be represented by a utility
function with expected utility form - Indifference curves
- Since the Von-Neuman-Morgestern utility is linear
in probabilities, if we represent the
indifference curves on the lottery space, we will
obtain parallel straight lines - If not straight lines indipendence axiom not
satisfied - If not parallel indipendence axiom not satisfied
10Consumer choice under uncertainty
- If preferences admit expected utility form
representation, then the consumer choice under
uncertainty reduces to the maximisation of his
expected utility, given his budget constraint
11Money Lottery and risk adversion
- Solving problems under uncertainty we can see
that individuals show some degree of risk
aversion - Where does risk aversion come from?
- In other words, which property of the utility
function in the expected utility framework
implies risk aversion? - Suppose that we define utility over monetary
lotteries. Let x be certain amount of money an
individual receives - And u(x) the utility associated x. We can show
that risk aversion is implies by CONCAVITY of
u(x).UNIQUENESS - Is the utility function unique?
- NO - - ANY MONOTONIC TRANSFORMATION REPRESENTS
THE SAME PREFERENCES - UTILITY IS AN ORDINAL CONCEPT NOT A CARDINAL
CONCEPT!
12Utility function
Risk aversion
13Utility function
14Risk Aversion
- Risk aversion can also be seen using two other
concepts - Certainty equivalent the sure amount of money
that you are willing to accept instead of the
lottery - Probability premium the excess in probability
over fair odds that makes an individual
indifferent between a certain outcome and a
gamble - If an individual is risk averse you expect that
- The sure amount of money he is willing to accept
instead of the gamble should be less then the
expected value of the money he would get from the
gamble (he is willing to take less and avoid the
risk) - An individual accepts the risk only if he is
offered better than fair odds
15Measures of Risk Aversion
16Measures of Risk Aversion
17Risky choices
Risky Choices
- Examples of risky choices
- Insurance
- Investment in risky asset
- Comparisons of different payoffs
- Suppose that you are faced with the choice of
comparing different risky investments - Which type of statistics about the lottery would
you use to choose among investments?
18Risky Choices
- level of return (average)
- dispersion of returns
- If you know the distribution function, you can
use this information to compare lotteries
19Stochastic dominance
- First order stochastic dominance F(.)
first-order stochastically dominates G(.) if
20Stochastic dominance
- Now, suppose that you can change F(.) in a way
that preserves the mean but changes the variance.
Suppose that G(.) is the function that you obtain
from this transformation, that is G(.) is a
mean-preserving spread of F(.) - Ex F(.) such that with probability p1/2 you get
2 and with prob p1/2 you get 3, hence the
average payoff is 5/2 - Let be G(.) such that with probability p1/4 you
can get (1,2,3,4) hence the average payoff is
again 5/2 - Would you prefer F(.) or G(.)?
21Stochastic dominance
- If you are risk averse, you will prefer F(.) to
G(.). - Indeed, we can prove that F(.) second-order
stochastically dominates G(.) - Definition
- Second order stochastic dominance given F(.) and
G(.) with the same mean, F(.) second-order
stochastically dominates (or is less risky than)
G(.) if
22Stochastic dominance
- Result if G(.) is a mean preserving spread of
F(.), then F(.) second-order stochastically
dominates G(.) - Proof
- Let x be a lottery distributed according to F(.).
Suppose that we further randomize x so that the
final payoff is xz where z is distributed
according the the function H(z) with zero mean.
Therefore, xz has the same mean as x but
different variance. We define G(.) final reduced
lottery, i.e. the function that is assigning a
probability to each x using the transformation of
F(.) we have just described. Hence G(.) is a mean
preserving spread of F(.).
23Stochastic dominance
24Expected Utility theory a calibration exercise
- Consider the following gamble
- You can loose 10 with probability 50 and gain
11 with probability 50 - Do you accept this gamble?
- Consider now these alternative gambles
- Loose 100 with 50 prob. and win 110 with 50
prob. - Loose 100 with probability 50 and win 221 with
50 prob. - Loose 100 with probability 50 and win 2000
with 50 prob. - Loose 100 with probability 50 and win 20,000
with 50 prob. - Loose 100 with probability 50 and win 1
million with 50 prob. - Loose 100 with probability 50 and win 2
millions with 50 prob. - Which bet will you be willing to accept?
25Source M. Rabin and R.H.Thaler (2001),
Anomalies- Risk Aversion, Journal of Economic
Perspectives, pages 219-232
26Expected Utility theory a calibration exercise
- Problem the expected utility theory delivers
implausible excessive degree of risk aversion!