Caveats on Readings and PowerPoint Presentations - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 67
About This Presentation
Title:

Caveats on Readings and PowerPoint Presentations

Description:

none – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:87
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 68
Provided by: itdepta
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Caveats on Readings and PowerPoint Presentations


1
Caveats on Readings and PowerPoint Presentations
  • The readings in Matters of Life and Death do not
    straightforwardly argue for one position or
    another because they are survey articles.
  • When you argue for one position, you should not
    mimic these readings. You should rather state
    your position first, and write only what you need
    to say in order to establish your position.
  • PowerPoint Presentations in the course generally
    do not try to follow and summarize what the
    authors of readings say. Presentations cover the
    same topics in a different organization and
    perspective from the readings do. They
    selectively engage with the readings and
    sometimes add new materials.

2
Assignments for Thursday
  • Read
  • Hugo Adam Bedau, 30 Equal Justice and Capital
    Punishment, 188-190 of the text
  • McCleskey v. Kemp in Library Reserve
  • Randall Kennedy, Homicide, Race, and Capital
    Punishment in Library Reserve
  • The Diagnostic Paper is due on Thursday. (See
    instructions on our website.)

3
Capital Punishment
  • 2006 Makoto Suzuki
  • Some of the materials are adapted from Prof.
    Donald Hubins handouts and presentations. The
    copy rights of them belongs to him.

4
Aims of Day 3
  • Introduce theoretical frameworks of death penalty
    disputes, and consider whether the state should
    give death penalty for certain individuals.
  • We proceed in the following order
  • Death penalty as a form of punishment
  • Moral rights and death penalty
  • Utilitarianism and death penalty
  • Retributivism and death penalty
  • The dignity of a person and death penalty

5
1. Death penalty as a form of punishment
6
Death Penalty as a Form of Punishment
  • Death penalty is a form of punishment. Thus, a
    promising approach to assessing capital
    punishment is to ask the following two questions
  • Do the considerations that justify punishment
    in general support death penalty?
  • Do the considerations that disqualify ways of
    punishment apply to death penalty?
  • If one takes this approach, then, as Bedau says
    on pp.169-70, We are not likely to assess the
    morality of capital punishment correctly unless
    we understand the morality of punishment in
    general.
  • Thus, we start with considering what
    considerations are relevant to assessment of
    punishment in general.

7
The Need for Justification (Bedau, 10, p.170)
  • Punishment stands in need of justification
    because
  • By definition, it involves the intentional
    infliction of pain or some other consequence
    normally considered unpleasant.
  • These undesirable consequences are typically
    inflicted against the wishes of the person
    punished.

8
Philosophical Problems in the Justification of
Punishment
  • General Justification
  • Is any system of punishment by the state morally
    justified? If so, upon what basis? (This
    involves considering alternative responses to
    crimee.g., therapeutic rehabilitation,
    reparation to victims etc.)
  • There are arguments for alternative responses
    over punishment, but we wont examine them. This
    is not because they are silly. Check the links
    above.
  • The Distribution of Punishment
  • Whom should we punish? Why? (This is sometimes
    called the question of title.)
  • How much should we punish and in what ways? Why?
    (This is sometimes called the question of
    severity.)

9
2. Moral rights and death penalty
10
Justifying Punishment Why Not Appeal to Moral
Rights?
  • Arguing for a moral claim, people often defend it
    on the basis of having or losing certain rights.
  • Ex Ray should pay money to Cathy because she
    has a right to be compensated for the damage he
    made.
  • So, justifying punishment, some might say
  • Criminals should be punished because they have
    forfeited their rights (Bedau, 162) or
  • Criminals should be punished because the
    society has a right to punish the guilty (Bedau,
    170)

11
Legal v. Moral Rights
  • The question is whether punishment is morally
    justified. So charity requires that we NOT
    interpret rights justifying (legal) punishment
    as legal rights.
  • If they are legal rights, it begs the question.
    Legal rights are determined by laws, and it is
    the moral justifiability of the (criminal) laws
    that is questioned.
  • Plausibly rights in this context are moral
    rights, which exist independently of laws.

12
Problems Specific to Using Moral Rights in
Justifying Punishment
  • Even if one of these claims is correct, it does
    not settle the question Should the state punish
    the guilty?
  • As Bedau points out (on 164-5), even if the
    guilty have forfeited their rights, taken alone,
    it does not imply (by sheer logic) that someone
    should punish them.
  • It just means that the guilty cannot claim to be
    entitled to certain things.
  • Even if the state has the right to punish the
    guilty, it does not entail that the state should
    punish them.
  • It just means that the state may punish them.
  • Even if one of these claims is correct, it does
    not settle the questions of severity How much
    should we punish and in what ways? Why?

13
Appeal to Rights General Problems
  • Many things about moral rights are controversial.
    Ex.
  • What kinds of rights there are? (Are there
    privacy rights, property or copy rights, rights
    to non-interference from others, rights to
    education, rights to clean air etc.?)
  • Whether the state has the right to punish is also
    controversial.
  • Can one transfer rights to others by consent, or
    forfeit them by doing certain things (like
    wrongs)? If so, can one lose any kind of rights,
    even the right to life?
  • So if you claim the guilty forfeit rights
    (including the right to life), you need an
    argument for the claim.
  • This is also true of the opponents claim that
    death penalty is prohibited because one cant
    lose the right to life.
  • Are all rights natural, i.e., does everyone has
    them merely being a person? Or are some or all
    rights non-natural, i.e., does the possession
    depend on social system (e.g., capitalism),
    personal merits, benefits it produces, etc.?

14
Continued
  • Who have rights? (Do fetuses or animals have
    rights?)
  • When two rights conflict, which right must
    prevail?
  • Are rights unlimited? (Can a person do anything
    to what she has rights to, e.g., her life, body,
    property, liberty? Are the rights valid beyond
    time and space? )
  • It seems that we cannot rationally settle these
    questions by appealing to moral rights.
  • Because of the general problems, we need to
    consider (1) the considerations that can justify
    claims of rights, and (2) the consideration that
    can limit claims of rights.
  • In the question of justifying punishment, (1) are
    primarily utility and desert. (2) is dignity as a
    person. So we will examine these considerations.

15
3. Utilitarianism and death penalty
16
Utilitarianism
  • Utilitarianism recommends an action, including
    punishment, if and only if it has the best
    effects on the well-being of the affected
    individuals.

17
Utilitarian Approach The General Justification
  • All punishment is, according to the utilitarian,
    intrinsically bad because it involves the
    infliction of pain or some other consequence
    normally considered unpleasant. Nevertheless,
    punishment by the state may be justified because
    of its effects that is, its instrumental
    benefits might outweigh the intrinsic badness.
  • According to utilitarians, the good consequences
    of punishment are the promotion of utility
    (happiness/pleasure/desire satisfaction).

18
Reduction in Crime
  • The consequences largely come through the
    reduction in crime.
  • The justification will only work for systems
    where reducing behavior classified as criminal
    will promote utility. Societies that criminalize
    behavior that is not harmful will have difficulty
    establishing that reducing the incidence of these
    sorts of be actions will produce utility.
  • Systems of punishment are usually claimed to
    reduce crime by three means
  • Deterrence
  • Incapacitation
  • Rehabilitation

19
  • Deterrence Deterrence refers to the reduction
    in crime as a result of making crime too costly
    to the would-be criminalpricing crime too
    high.
  • (a) Special The tendency of the punishment to
    deter the person punished from criminal acts.
  • (b) General The tendency of the punishment of
    one person to deter others from committing
    criminal acts.
  • Incapacitation Incapacitation refers to
    removal of the opportunity or ability of the
    potential criminal to commit criminal acts
    (sometimes only of a certain sort).
  • Rehabilitation (Reform) Rehabilitation takes
    place when the character of the person punished
    is altered so that he or she no longer desires to
    commit the sort of act for which he or she was
    punished.

20
Possible Effects Other than Reduction of Crimes
  • Through deterrence etc., the practice of
    punishment might tend to prevent crimes and hence
    the loss in peoples well-being.
  • Further, the practice of punishment might have
    other effects. For example
  • Punishment might make people feel safer (even if
    it actually does not do so).
  • Punishment might also satisfy the feelings of
    vengeance, resentment and indignation.
  • Whether satisfying feeling of vengeance etc.
    would have good consequences might be
    questionable. If so, it does not provide
    utilitarians with a reason for punishment.

21
Utilitarian Approach Distribution
  • 1. Title We should punish all and only those who
    it gives the best effects on utility to punish.
  • 2. Severity We should punish to the extent that
    produces the best effects on utility and no more.

22
Is Death Penalty Justified from the Utilitarian
Perspective?
  • Remember that from utilitarian perspective, a
    punishment must have the effects better than any
    other alternative has.
  • Thus, the question is does capital punishment
    have the effects better than any other
    alternative, e.g., life imprisonment without the
    possibility of parole, has?
  • How about deterrence? (Bedau, 181-2)
  • Special No effect, because the criminal does not
    survive.
  • General ? (Some statistical and clinical studies
    indicate death penalty has brutalization
    effects it incites certain unstable minds to
    murder others. Bedau, 182)

23
  • How about incapacitation? (Bedau, 179-80)
  • Perfect, but compare w/ life imprisonment. (cf,
    192.9)
  • How about rehabilitation?
  • No effect, because the criminal does not survive.
    Other punishment might have good or bad effects.
  • How about the sense of security?
  • How about satisfying the feelings of vengeance
    etc.?
  • How about the cost of practicing death penalty?
  • The cost of executing a person is not expensive.
    (I do not know about life imprisonment letting a
    person play will cost much, but making her work
    might cut the cost.)
  • However, a study suggests that in the US, the
    legal system w/ court trials and appeals on death
    penalty costs far more than the legal system w/o
    them. (Richard Dieter, Millions Misspent, 1994)
  • Other costs or benefits?

24
Alleged Problems of the Utilitarian Justification
of Punishment
  • A. Because the utilitarian answers the question
    of severity as she does, she may allow for more
    or less punishment than is deservedno punishment
    even for severe crimes if it does not have the
    best effects severe punishment for trivial
    crimes if we could get a lot of benefit from it.
  • B. Because the utilitarian answers the question
    of title as she does, she may justify punishing
    an innocent person as easily as a guilty person.
    If the effect on crime prevention is equal,
    actual guilt or innocence is irrelevant.

25
Continued
  • C. Because the utilitarian offers the general
    justification of punishment she does, even where
    she gives the right answer about title and
    severity, she gives it for what is arguably the
    wrong reason.
  • a utilitarian theory of punishment must
    involve justifying punishment in terms of its
    social resultse.g., deterrence, incapacitation,
    and rehabilitation. And thus even a guilty man
    is, on this theory, being punished because of the
    instrumental value the action of punishment will
    have in the future. He is being used as a means
    to some future good e.g., the deterrence of
    others. Thus those of a Kantian persuasion, who
    see the importance of worrying about the
    treatment of persons as mere means, must, it
    would seem, object just as strenuously to the
    punishment of the guilty on utilitarian grounds
    as to the punishment of the innocent. (Jeffrie,
    G. Murphy, Marxism and Retribution)

26
4. Retributivism and death penalty
27
Retributivism
  • Retributivism justifies actions, including
    punishment, in terms of the desert of the
    criminal based on his or her past behavior,
    intention etc.
  • Retributive theories differ on what makes an
    agent deserves a bad result like punishment the
    harm the agent causes, her wickedness, the fact
    that she unfairly exploit other members of her
    society, etc.
  • Retributive theories thus differ on two questions
    of distribution (1) title who should be
    punished and (2) severity how much should a
    person be punished, and why.

28
Pure Retributive Approach The General
Justification and Distribution
  • However, there are folliwng agreements among pure
    retributivists, who take desert as the only
    factor in justifying punishment.
  • Desert is the sole general justification of
    punishment by the state.
  • Distribution
  • Title One should punish only those who are
    guilty, i.e., who deserve punishement.
  • Severity One should punish the guilty to the
    extent they deserve.

29
A Standard of the Distribution of Punishment lex
talionis (Bedau, 186-8)
  • lex talionis is the standard of both title and
    severity
  • Title the agent who caused harm is guilty and
    should be punished.
  • Severity the agent should be given the
    punishment that provides the same type of harm
    that he or she caused.
  • A problem as the standard of title there are
    some cases where an agent causes harm, but he
    should not be punished.
  • Ex. Certain cases of self- or other- defense
    harms for which the agents cannot be responsible

30
The Problems of lex tarionis as the Standard of
Severity
  • lex tarionis does not take into account the
    intention or motive of the suspect. E.g. Even if
    deliberate or planned killing justifies death
    penalty for the suspect, non-deliberate killing,
    particularly unintentional killing, might not
    justify it. (Cf. Bedau, 27, 186)
  • Giving exactly the same harm is impossible.
    (Bedau, 28) Even giving roughly the same harm is
    frequently impossible or makes no sense and
    sometimes is repugnant.
  • E.g. What punishment should be given to child
    molesters? To speeders and drunk drivers? To
    embezzlers and forgers? To prostitutes and their
    customers? To rapists? To T.V. ministers who
    violate their trust by defrauding their flock out
    of millions of dollars?

31
Which Standards of Title?
  • As is mentioned earlier, retributivists differ on
    the standard of title (1) the harm the agent
    causes lex tarionis takes this view , (2) her
    wickedness, (3) the fact that she unfairly
    exploit other members of her society, or (4) some
    combination of them etc.
  • Settling this point is important when one
    considers who, if any, should deserve death
    penalty.
  • Bedau favors the third option. (11, pp.170-1)
    However, unless you are interested in his
    argument for the option, we will not examine it.
    For our focus is a prior question should death
    penalty be given (to whatever person)?

32
An Alternative Standard of Severity to lex
tarionis Well-Being
  • While Bedau criticizes lex tarionis as a theory
    of severity (186-8), he does provides no
    alternative.
  • An alternative is the well-being standard of
    severity.
  • Its rough idea is as follows the more guilty a
    person is, the more loss of well-being does the
    person deserve.
  • Pure retributivism with this standard holds that
    a guilty person should be given the punishment
    that makes the persons life proportionally
    worse-off.
  • One complaint might be that it gives no reason to
    choose among punishments giving the loss of
    well-being the guilty deserves. (E.g., why
    imprisonment rather than slave labor, removing
    the penis, raping, maiming, beating etc.?)
  • But it is at least better than lex tarionis,
    which requires things impossible (child molesting
    for child molesting, drunk driving for drunk
    driving etc.) or repugnant (torture for torture
    etc.).

33
Pure Retributivism and Death Penalty
  • Does death penalty give the guilty what he or she
    deserves?
  • This question can of course depend on what the
    guilty is guilty of.
  • lex tarionis is often used to justify death
    penalty for murderers. (As Bedau points out on
    p.186, it disqualifies death penalty for other
    actions.) However, for the reasons mentioned
    above, this standard of severity is problematic.
  • If the standard of severity is how much
    punishment lowers the level of well-being, does
    death penalty (rather than life imprisonment
    etc.) fit the crime in some cases?

34
Is Death Penalty Particularly Severe?
  • This partly depends on the way it is executed.
  • From stoning, crucifixion, impalement, beheading,
    hanging, shooting, gas chamber, electrocution to
    painless lethal injection
  • However, death penalty essentially involves
    shortening of life. (Bedau, 14, 173)
  • Bedau says the shortening of life is particularly
    severe. Why?

35
Bedau on the particularly severity of death
penalty
  • Once death penalty is executed, it is
    interminable while it is possible to interrupt
    the execution of some (though not all) other
    punishments, e.g. imprisonment. (Bedau, 16, 176)
  • Death penalty makes compensation for the proven
    innocent impossible. (ibid.)
  • But compensation for her friends and families is
    possible.
  • People punished by other means might die before
    proven innocent.
  • Also consider whether the proven innocent can be
    fully compensated for other punishments, such as
    imprisonment.

36
Continued
  • Death does not permit of no concurrent
    experiences or activities. (ibid.)
  • True, but cant the experiences or activities
    possible under other modes of punishment be worse
    than nothing?
  • All in all, is death penalty severer than other
    modes of punishment?

37
Should We Accept Pure Retributivism? One Thought
Experiment
  • Imagine that each of the nearly five billion
    humans were to exit Earth in solo spacecraft,
    which goes in different directions and never
    meets any sentient creature again. There are the
    guilty in prisons, and people wonder what to do
    with them.
  • Assuming that other things are equali.e., that
    there is no effect on the happiness of others,
    should all of the guilty be punished?
  • If you answers no, the response is inconsistent
    with pure retributivism. Are utilitarians correct
    to the extent that punishment is partly justified
    by effects on peoples well-being?

38
Interlude Why think of bizarre cases?
  • We would like to check one feature (in this case,
    desert) makes difference independently of other
    factors (e.g., social defense). We cannot check
    this thinking about ordinary cases because they
    involve not only the feature in question but also
    other factors.
  • The unrealistic example is made to include only
    the feature in question (in this case, desert).
  • Our views about ordinary examples are likely to
    reflect what we were taught. Because the views
    different people were taught conflicts with each
    other and can be suspicious, we probably cant
    settle our dispute rationally by thinking about
    ordinary cases.
  • Our responses about somewhat bizarre cases are
    less likely to be the mere reflection of what we
    were taught. We might find agreement in our
    responses and settle our dispute rationally.

39
Other Problems of Pure Retributivism
  • About the general justification of punishment
  • 1. pure retributivism gives no good reason why
    the state, rather than other individuals or
    organs, should punish the guilty.
  • 2. related to the above, pure retributivism
    excludes the states apparently legitimate
    interest in preventing criminal actions through
    administrating the system of punishment, e.g.,
    jail system.

40
About the severity of punishment
  • 1.pure retributivism excludes several
    considerations that juries and prosecutors appeal
    to e.g., the possibility of a second offense and
    reform, effects on crime prevention, security or
    how people will regard the allegedly criminal
    actions, the suspect and the court, and so on.
  • 2.pure retributivism invalidates many legal
    practices, e.g., commutation based on
    rehabilitation, clemency and plea bargaining (in
    which a person charged with a crime pleads guilty
    and cooperate with prosecutors in exchange for a
    less severe sentence than he might have received
    if his case went to trial and he was found
    guilty).

41
Unifying Utilitarian and Retributive Elements?
  • Thus, theories w/ both elements might be
    appealing. For example
  • Retributive Consequentialism (RC) On this
    theory, retribution (as well as increasing
    peoples well-being) is a good consequence. RC
    recommends an action, including punishment, if
    and only if it has the best effects, taking into
    both kinds of value.
  • Unless you are interested in RC, we do not
    discuss the merits of the theory.
  • For theories w/ both elements, both utilitarian
    issues (deterrence etc.) and issues about desert
    are relevant to assessing actions like punishment.

42
Retributive Theory and Punishing the Innocent
  • For any theory w/ the factor of desert,
    punishing the innocent is particularly bad, i.e.,
    worse than punishing the guilty.
  • If a criminal justice system is unfair or
    ineffective at punishing only the real criminals,
    it (with the system of punishment) can be
    unjustified.
  • Because human beings are often partial and
    uninformed, any criminal justice system operated
    by human beings will punish some innocent.

43
Killing the Innocent v. Having Them by Punished
Other Means
  • According to Bedau and Radelet 1987, in the 20th
    century US, out of over 7,000 executions, only a
    few hundred have been carefully examined, and of
    these .3 percents (24 cases) seem to have
    executed the innocent. (Note on 22 on 194)
  • Since 1973, more than 90 have been released from
    death rows.
  • The use of DNA testing can help avoiding
    punishing the innocent. As of June 2002, 12 death
    row inmates have been exonerated by use of DNA
    tests. But it is not free of problems.
  • Then, should death penalty be abolished?
  • Remember, even if death penalty is abolished, the
    innocent might well be found guilty and
    punished by other means.
  • The answer depends on whether there is a reason
    to have the innocent punished by other admissible
    means than death.
  • What are other admissible means? To see this
    point, we need to consider another consideration
    possibly relevant to justification of punishment
    the dignity of a person.

44
5. The dignity of a person and death penalty
45
Why We May Not Abuse the Guilty Appeal to the
Dignity of a Person?
  • To many it seems that if a form of punishment
    disfigures a body, is cruel or humiliating, then
    it is morally unjustified.
  • Pure retributivists have trouble justifying this
    judgment.
  • How about utilitarians? Does the negative effects
    exist?
  • Getting people used to cruelty, brutalization
    effects etc.?
  • If you think the form of punishment is
    unjustified and these two cannot support the
    judgment, you might appeal to the dignity of a
    person because the form of punishment offends
    the dignity, it is unjustified.
  • Caution If you use this reasoning, some forms of
    punishment had better not offend the dignity.
    Otherwise, all forms of punishments will be
    unjustified. (Dont follow Bedau saying,
    Punishment by its nature pays back an
    offenderby inflicting suffering and indignity
    (171))

46
What the Heck Dignity Mean?
  • The big problem of appealing to the dignity of a
    person is that it is not clear what it means, and
    accordingly why it is important and whether cruel
    or humiliating punishment really offends it.
  • If you can explain these points, try.
  • To many dignity sounds like a mere rhetoric. They
    thus avoid talking about dignity.
  • Immanuel Kant tried explicating this difficult
    idea.

47
Kant on the Dignity of a Person
  • According to Kant, the dignity of a person
    consists in her being a rational and autonomous
    agent.
  • If one treats the person in the way a person, as
    a rational and autonomous agent, can never
    consent to, then he uses her merely as a means,
    i.e., offends the dignity of the person.
  • Kant holds that a person, as a rational and
    autonomous agent, can consent to being punished
    for what she has done because such an agent takes
    responsibility for her action and consequences.
  • However, Kant also holds that a person, as a
    rational and autonomous agent, cannot consent to
    certain forms of punishment. For example, she
    cannot consent to being punished merely for
    future benefits and not for her wrong actions.
  • So Kant has a reason to reject utilitarianism.

48
Questions
  • Can a person, as a rational and autonomous agent,
    really consent to his or her punishment?
  • This question depends on what rationality and
    autonomy involves. If, e.g., as economists say,
    rational and autonomous agents are maximizers of
    their desires, then they cannot consent to their
    punishment.
  • Suppose a person, as a rational and autonomous
    agent, can consent to her punishment of certain
    sort say, imprisonment because they are
    responsible. Cant she also consent to the
    punishment that disfigures her body, is cruel, or
    humiliating for what she has done?
  • Many criminals have mental problems and neither
    fully rational nor autonomous. (Bedau, 6 7,
    167-8) What does Kants view of dignity say about
    punishing them?
  • Does Kants view of dignity prohibit death
    penalty?

49
Bedau on Kant on Appeal to Utility
  • Bedau might be mistaken in taking Kants view on
    dignity (i.e., the view that one should not be
    used merely as a means) excludes any theory
    involving appeal to effect on peoples
    well-being. (p.166, 2nd paragraph)
  • The view clearly excludes punishing a person
    merely for peoples well-being, but it is perhaps
    consistent with punishing her not only for it but
    also for what she has done.
  • So, it is inconsistent with utilitarianism, but
    perhaps not with certain theories that have
    utilitarian elements.

50
The Problem of Killing the Innocent, again
  • Should death penalty be abolished for this
    problem?
  • If you think that brutal, cruel or humiliating
    punishments are permissible, do you think there
    is a reason to let the innocent punished that
    way?
  • If you think, for the considerations of dignity
    etc., that these punishments are not permissible,
    do you think there is a reason to let the
    innocent punished by, say, life imprisonment w/o
    parole?

51
Finale Unfair Justice and Capital Punishment
52
Alleged Unfairness with which Punishment is
Applied
  • There has been a concern about whether the US
    criminal court system passes sentence
    arbitrarily.
  • The worry is that the sentence is affected by the
    things that are judged irrelevant by all the
    theories we have studied utilitarianism,
    retributivism and the idea of the dignity of a
    person.
  • There are two kinds of worries worries about (1)
    some legal statues and principles and about (2)
    the application of them.

53
1. The Concern about Legal Standards
  • Arent some legal standards so hollow and
    prosecutors and juries discretion so large that
    similar suspects are sentenced differently?
    (Bedau, 27, 186-7)
  • E.g.1 the distinction between 1st degree and 2nd
    degree murder (In some states, juries are told
    that premeditation can occur in a single instant)
  • E.g.2 it is said that no articulate standard
    controls a prosecutors discretionary decision to
    bring capital charges in the first place or to
    reject a plea to a lesser offense.

54
2. Isnt the application of the standards
affected by irrelevant factors?
  • In particular, there are worries about two
    factors
  • Doesnt the wealth of the suspect affect his or
    her sentence?
  • Doesnt race affect the suspects sentence?
  • (Other factors, such as the difference of the
    jurisdictions the suspects are tried, might be
    irrelevant but affect the sentence.)

55
How Might Wealth Affect the Ultimate Sentence?
  • Wealth might affect whether the suspect can hire
    good, experienced and non-overworked counsel
  • Wealth might affect whether the suspect has funds
    to bring sympathetic witnesses to courts
  • Wealth might affect whether the suspect has funds
    for an appeal or for a transcript of the trial
    record and so on.

56
How Might Race Affect the Sentence? Typical
Worries
  • Isnt there a tendency that the suspect is
    sentenced more severely when the suspect is a
    black than when the suspect is a white?
  • Isnt there a tendency that the suspect is
    sentenced more severely when the victim is a
    white than when the victim is a black?
  • Or their combination isnt there a tendency that
    the suspect is sentenced more severely when the
    suspect is a black and the victim is a white?
  • In addition isnt there a tendency that the
    suspect is sentenced more severely when the
    suspect is a black (or a white) and the majority
    of the jury is white (or black). (See the movie
    Time to Kill, 1996 see also p. 498 of Randall
    Kennedys paper on what the Supreme Court did
    about a related issue.)

57
Death Penalty and Race
  • As for death penalty, (1) the relation between
    the race of the suspect and the sentence is not
    substantiated. As for (3), see McCleskey v. Kemp
    on the Baldus study (p.491). I dont know about
    (4).
  • But a 1990 review of then existing research by
    the US governments General Accounting Office
    reported that In 82 percent of the studies, race
    of victim was found to influence the likelihood
    of being charged with capital murder or receiving
    the death penalty.
  • According to Bedau 1997, this finding is
    remarkably consistent across data sets, states,
    data collection methods, and analytic
    techniques.
  • Controlling for a variety of legitimate, relevant
    non-racial variables reduced but not eliminate
    the evidence of race-of-victim bias.

58
An Example The Baldus Study
  • The Baldus study consists of statistical studies
    that examine over 2,000 murder cases in Georgia
    during the 1970s.
  • Baldus subjected his data to an extensive
    analysis, taking account of 230 variables that
    could have explained the disparities on nonracial
    grounds. One of his models concludes that, even
    after taking account of 39 non-racial variables,
    defendants charged with killing white victims
    were 4.3 times as likely to receive a death
    sentence as defendants charged with killing
    blacks. (McCleskey v. Kemp, pp.491-2)
  • The race of victim is as strongly correlated with
    giving or not giving death sentence as a prior
    murder conviction or acting as the principal
    planner of the homicide is. (ibid., p.493)
  • Racial disparities are greatest in what Baldus
    takes to be the middle range of aggravated
    homicide.

59
What should be done?
  • Suppose that (1) the legal principles and (2)
    their applications in the US Justice System have
    been partly arbitrary and unfair.
  • There would be an obvious problem of how to make
    the system as a whole more fair.
  • However, it is hard to discuss this question
    meaningfully without the sufficient knowledge of
    the current system and of how legislature and the
    court work. So I leave it aside unless someone
    wants to talk about the topic.
  • There is another specific question about what to
    do with the practice of death penalty.

60
Should We Abolish Death Penalty for Being
Arbitrary?
  • This question partly depends on whether the
    arbitrariness or unfairness is peculiar to the
    legal principles and the application of death
    penalty.
  • If the answer is no, even if death penalty is
    abolished, it is likely that the replacement
    (say, life imprisonment w/o parole) will be as
    arbitrarily or unfairly given.
  • This does not automatically mean that the
    abolition will be senseless.
  • For example, if you hold the view that the
    justification of the severer modes of punishments
    require the more non-arbitrary and fair
    principles or application, and think that death
    penalty is severer than any other admissible
    modes of punishments, you have some reason to
    abolish death penalty.

61
How the Defenders of Death Penalty Respond
(Bedau, 30, 189)
  • Summarize concisely what they would say
  • The statues that authorize death penalty
    themselves are not unfair only the current
    application might be. So the alleged unfairness
    is not an objection to the morality of death
    penalty itself.
  • Is this reply adequate?
  • First, this reply does not address the alleged
    problems about legal principles, e.g., the
    distinction between 1st degree murder and 2nd
    degree murder.
  • But the defenders can say Why not fix the
    principles and keep death penalty?
  • Second, the adequacy of this response depends on
    whether there is a better alternative to the
    abolition of death penalty. So we will consider
    several alternatives Randall Kennedy discusses.

62
Alternatives (Kennedy, 498-500)
  • Total Abolition.
  • Level-up Solution have the courts execute more
    in the cases where the victims are black (and
    perhaps in the cases where the suspect is rich
    also fix problematic standards, if any).
  • Limiting the class of persons eligible for
    execution to those who commit the most aggravated
    homicides. (Also fix problematic standards, if
    any.)
  • Introducing the mandatory execution of those
    sentenced for certain crimes.
  • (Basically keeping the status quo, fixing
    problematic standards, if any)

63
4. Introducing the mandatory execution of those
sentenced for certain crimes.
  • Concisely summaries the reasons why the Supreme
    Court rejected this in 1976. (499)
  • It encourages juries to share their verdicts to
    avoid sentencing the suspect to the crimes.
  • It fails to takes into account the suspects
    individuality (intentions, motives etc.) for
    committing the crimes.
  • Concisely summaries the two reasons why Kennedy
    rejects this alternative. (499)
  • The racial disparity might remain, because the
    juries might decline to convict the suspect of
    the crimes when the victim is a black.
  • The racial disparity might remain, because the
    prosecutors will keep the same discretion as they
    have now.

64
3. Limiting the class of persons eligible for
execution
  • According to Kennedy, what is the problem of this
    approach (suggested by Justice Stevens and
    Blackmun)? (499)
  • It is practically impossible to provide objective
    standards or procedures to select all and only
    those who commit the most aggravated homicides.
  • Is this correct?
  • Not so obviously. For example, consider the
    suggestion that limits death penalty to those who
    kill more than two people.

65
2. Level-up Solution
  • Kennedy ultimately recommends this solution (for
    the defenders of death penalty). However, he
    suggests objections. What are they? (499-500)
  • It tends to give more than what the suspect
    deserves.
  • Kennedy indicates that severity may or should
    reflect the effects on peoples utility, and that
    the level-up solution have the good effects (by
    encouraging officials to take more seriously the
    security of blacks and symbolically showing the
    importance of racial equality to the public.) Is
    he right about this judgment?
  • In particular, the severity of death is
    qualitatively different from other modes of
    punishment, so it is too harsh a social sanction
    to impose upon those who deserve lesser sentence.
  • Kennedy denies that the severity of death is
    qualitatively different from other modes of
    punishment. Is he right?

66
The Last Question
  • All things considered, should the state give
    capital punishment on some occasion?
  • If so, how?

67
Assignments
  • For Thursday, read
  • Onora ONeill, Ending World Hunger, 235-58
    1-8 of Questions for Discussion on p.277
  • For Tuesday, write a one-page Argument Paper.
  • Give the best possible argument for or against
    the following claim Death penalty should be
    abolished because the criminal justice system is
    unfair.
  • (If you think that death penalty should be
    abolished but for other reasons than the
    unfairness of the system, you should argue
    against the above claim.)
  • If you argue against this claim, show the
    superiority of some alternative in dealing with
    the unfairness.
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com