The Nature of Desire and the Debate over Internal and External Reasons: A New Way Forward - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 47
About This Presentation
Title:

The Nature of Desire and the Debate over Internal and External Reasons: A New Way Forward

Description:

Don't make it a matter of course, but as a remarkable fact, that pictures and ... It is just as if you should fall in love with one of the sparrows which fly by ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:131
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 48
Provided by: peterr97
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: The Nature of Desire and the Debate over Internal and External Reasons: A New Way Forward


1
The Nature of Desire and the Debate over Internal
and External Reasons A New Way Forward?
  • Peter Railton
  • University of Oslo
  • May 2009

2
  • Napoleon
  • Imagination rules the world.
  • Wittgenstein
  • Dont make it a matter of course, but as a
    remarkable fact, that pictures and fictions give
    us pleasure, occupy our minds.

3
A critical diagnosis
  • At the middle of the 20th century, two
    philosophers, W.K. Frankena and W.D. Falk
    independently offered a diagnosis of the most
    basic dispute underlying contemporary
    meta-ethics the connection between normative
    judgments and motivation.
  • They pointed out that this underlies the split
    between cognitivists (Moore, Ross, Prichard) and
    non-cognitivists (Ayer, Stevenson, Hare).

4
What is this connection?
  • According to the non-cognitivists, there is a
    necessary, semantic connection between making a
    moral judgment and having some degree of
    motivation to act in accordance with this
    judgment.
  • Thus, necessarily, anyone making a sincere moral
    judgment of the form
  • A ought to F
  • is expressing a state of mind that has positive
    motivational force for A toward doing F,
    encouraging others to do F, etc. A pro-attitude
    toward F-ing.

5
Why this connection?
  • This connection offers a seemingly
    straightforward explanation of a number of facts
    about moral discourse and practice
  • Why it is seen as a matter of insincerity to make
    a moral judgment but not show any tendency to act
    in accord with it.
  • Why it would seem to be a failure to grasp moral
    concepts to fail to see this.
  • How moral thought and language could be, by their
    nature, practical, i.e., could influence the
    will.
  • Why moral conflicts seemed to be conflicts in
    attitude, not resolvable by a simple appeal to
    the facts.

6
Every benefit has its costs
  • If the state of mind expressed by sincere moral
    judgment is, necessarily, motivating for the
    speaker, then we cannot treat this state of mind
    as a belief.
  • Why not?
  • Beliefs have representational content, and are
    true just in case their propositional objects are
    true.
  • But no proposition semantically entails
    motivation otherwise, it could not have
    orthodox truth conditions.
  • As a result, moral judgments could not be
    assigned orthodox truth conditions.
  • But we ordinarily do speak of moral judgments as
    true or false, use them in logical inference, etc.

7
Frankena and Falk were right
  • The next half-century in meta-ethics were taken
    up trying to sort this out.
  • Could a non-propositional account of the content
    of moral judgments capture the logical behavior
    of moral judgments? Or explain how they come to
    be seen as true or false?
  • Could a propositional account of the content of
    moral judgments capture the connection between
    moral judgment and motivation? Or explain why
    morality has the dynamical personal and social
    functions it does in shaping conduct?

8
The current terrain, deadlocked
  • Several dominant and seemingly stable, but
    conflicting, views have emerged, among them
  • Motivational judgment internalism the original,
    conceptual connection between moral judgment and
    motivation
  • Moral-reasons internalism the idea that the
    relation between moral judgments and motivation
    is normative not semantic, i.e., if one makes a
    moral judgment and is rational, one will be
    motivated
  • Motivational judgment externalism the
    connection between moral judgment and motivation
    is essentially contingent, though perhaps highly
    regular and typical of almost all agents in
    virtue of highly general facts about human
    psychology.

9
Some favorite examples
  • The sensible knave and inverted commas usages
  • a normative kind theorist should not be a
    hard-line, metaethical "externalist", who thinks
    that a "sensible knave" or "irrationalist" might
    fully share our normative concepts but not at all
    be guided in terms of them.   Anyone who
    "doesn't give a damn", for whom no question of
    action, actual or hypothetical, hinges on the
    classification, can't join into the conversation
    as full-fledged participant.  His use of this
    kind of language can only be parasitic on the
    usage of those who care.  Would a serenade be
    harassing as well as quaint?  The sensible cad
    might predict how people will classify serenades,
    or role-play at entering the discussion.  But it
    is puzzling what he is doing if he earnestly
    tries to take sides.  There is no such
    intelligible thing as pure theoretical curiosity
    in these matters. Gibbard 2003

10
Some favorite examples
  • The depressive
  • The amoralist

11
Which kind of internalism?
  • At the same time, however, a quite different
    debate over internalism and externalism has
    arisen, starting with a classic essay by Bernard
    Williams, Internal and External Reasons
  • Williams was concerned with so-called external
    reason attributions attribution to someone of a
    reason to act that had no resonance in that
    individuals subjective motivational set.
  • It struck him that such attributions were mere
    bluff, they could not identify a reason for
    him, since they could not make this action, goal,
    etc. intelligible to him as an extension of what
    he cares about, values, or could come to care
    about or value through a sound deliberative
    route.

12
This is a fundamentally different kind of
internalism
  • This sort of internalism about reasons makes
    the following sort of claim as a matter of
    metaphysical necessity
  • Necessarily, if B has a reason to F, then it is
    in principle possible for B to be led by a sound
    deliberative route to be motivated favorably
    toward F-ing
  • Therefore, necessarily, if A judges that B has a
    reason to F, and no such connection to Bs
    motivations can be made, As claim is false.
  • Note that this is a third-personal requirement,
    not a first-personal requirement on the sincerity
    of the speakers claim that A has a reason to F.
  • It is a matter of Bs subjective motivational
    set, not the speakers
  • And it is entirely consistent with reasons
    judgments possessing orthodox truth conditions of
    a perspective-independent kind.

13
Existence internalism Some motivations
  • Since it is a position on the existence
    conditions for reasons to act, this view is
    called motivational existence internalism.
  • It can be defended on at least three grounds
  • Reasons attributions have an explanatory role
  • Reasons attributions ought to be justifiable to
    the agent
  • Ought implies can

14
A conflict?
  • But existence internalism pulls us in quite a
    different direction from the original judgment
    internalism.
  • Consider the supposed truism
  • Necessarily, if A morally ought to F, then F has
    a reason to F
  • The reason must at least be important, perhaps
    overriding. It certainly must be As reason so
    that A would be acting contrary to reason if A
    failed to F.
  • On some views, this is the core of morality it
    is a form of pure practical rationality.
  • But this constrains moral judgment by a
    3rd-personal motivational condition, not
    guaranteed by the 1st-personal.

15
Methodological consideration
  • We should be doubtful about philosophical claims
    with very sweeping implications when we cannot
    identify a stable conception of what the claim
    is.
  • This seems to be the case with the connection
    between morality and motivation.
  • So how to go forward?
  • Today I will be focusing on the question, how to
    go forward in the debate on internal vs. external
    reasons.
  • There might be time for a hint at the end about
    the debate over judgment vs. existence
    internalims.

16
Look under the hood
  • I will be claiming that forward movement is
    obstructed by a failure to go deeply enough into
    the nature of the supposed mental states involved
    e.g., belief and desire.
  • This has unnecessarily restricted our options.
  • Some presuppositions of the debate
  • Beliefs are inert representations
  • Desires lack representational content
  • Desires cannot be more or less rational
  • I believe all of these claims are false.

17
Where we are
  • On Wednesday, I introduced a model of belief as
    affect-involving in a way that showed why beliefs
    are not inert representations.
  • In this I rejected the neo-Humean theory of
    motivation and returned to Humes original view
  • in philosophy we can go no farther, than
    assert, that belief is something felt by the
    mind, which distinguishes the ideas of the
    judgment from the fictions of the imagination. It
    gives them more force and influence makes them
    appear of greater importance infixes them in the
    mind and renders them the governing principles
    of all our actions. Treatise of Human Nature

18
Belief
  • be lief
  • be- leafa
  • about trust, faith, love

19
Credence
  • cre dence
  • kerd-
  • heart

20
Confidence
  • con fidence
  • kom- bheidh-
  • with trust, faith

21
True, Trust
  • dreu-
  • firm, steady

22
Belief
  • Belief that R
  • A degree of confidence (trust) in a
    representation R functions to regulate a degree
    of expectation that things are or will be as R
    portrays them and this degree of confidence in
    turn is modulated by whether in subsequent
    experience this expectation is met or violated.

23
(No Transcript)
24
New school Dual Process psychology affect
upstream from perceptual belief, directly
productive of behavior
25
What of Desire?Return to the functionalist
starting point
  • Belief and desire are correlative dispositional
    states of a potentially rational agent. To
    desire that P is to be disposed to act in ways
    that would tend to bring it about that P in a
    world in which ones beliefs, whatever they are,
    were true. To believe that P is to be disposed
    to act in ways that would tend to satisfy ones
    desires, whatever they are, in a world in which P
    (together with ones other beliefs) were true.
    Stalnaker, 1984

26
de sire
  • de- sider-
  • apart, away star

27
Kant on the good will
  • Even if it should happen that, owing to special
    disfavour of fortune, or the niggardly provision
    of a step-motherly nature, this will should
    wholly lack power to accomplish its purpose, if
    with its greatest efforts it should yet achieve
    nothing, and there should remain only the good
    will (not, to be sure, a mere wish, but the
    summoning of all means in our power), then, like
    a jewel, it would still shine by its own light,
    as a thing which has its whole value in itself.
    Groundwork, 394

28
Incentive
  • in ? centive
  • in- canere
  • into song

29
Kant on desire, life, and will
  • Desire and life
  • The faculty of desire is the faculty to be, by
    means of ones representations, the cause of the
    objects of those representations. The faculty of
    being able to act in accordance with its
    representations is called life.
  • Metaphysics of Morals 6211

30
Marx on humanity
  • The operations carried out by a spider resemble
    those of a weaver, and many a human architect is
    put to shame by the bee in the construction of
    its wax cells. However, the poorest architect is
    categorically distinguished from the best of bees
    by the fact that before he builds a cell in wax,
    he has built it in his head. (Marx, Capital)

31
Desire
  • Desire that R
  • A degree of positive affect toward a
    representation R functions to regulate a degree
    of positive motivation toward bringing about the
    state of affairs that R portrays and this degree
    of affect is subsequently modulated by whether
    actual experience of moving toward or realizing R
    is better, worse, or in conformity with
    expectations arising from the affective
    representation.

32
(No Transcript)
33
Some of desires features
  • Desire, when conscious, typically involves a
    desirability feature
  • Desire comes in degrees of strength, and has two
    senses two naïve notions of wanting, which
    can come apart, which are normally coupled in a
    regulative way. Two psychologically more
    primitive states physiological evidence.
  • Deire has a positive front end compare the
    itch theory
  • Like belief, desire shapes the allocation of
    attention, thought, and forward-going action
  • Like belief, desire creates expectation and leads
    to learning through feedback
  • Like belief, desires structure quips it for
    attunement.

34
Some of desires dysfunctions
  • A number of phenomena we think of as
    irrationality in desire can be understood as
    dysregulation or dysfunction of this
    representation-centered, affect-based
    feedforward-feedback system
  • Opaque desires and compulsions Quinns radio
    man
  • Addiction the reluctant addict
  • Change without learning when affect is
    systematically altered (depression and mania)
  • Suggestibility and advertising spurious
    desires and miswanting
  • Weakness of will - Wishing and wanting,
    salience and preference reversals

35
Conditioned response, affective forecasting,
and error learning to like and unlearning
36
Value-coded cognitive mapping foraging for
value
37
Desire and acting for reasons
  • The authority of desire Like belief, desire
    is a default, defeasible attitude that orients
    action without this, action would seem not to
    be possible (problems of regress).
  • This does not threaten rationality, or acting for
    a reason. Rather, it permits practical
    attunement to reasons without leading to regress.
  • Why informed desires have more authority, why
    they can contribute to the rationality of action
  • Desire also is part of affective primacy it
    contributes to evaluative perception or
    affordances.
  • It also enables us to see reasons and act
    accordingly, without needing to add any further
    desire.

38
Emotional intelligence and cognitive tuning
  • Belief, desire, and emotion all orient and help
    regulate subsequent thought and action, in part
    thanks to affective mechanisms
  • This orientation and regulation reflects the
    strength of affect strength of confidence,
    liking, or feeling
  • This orientation involves guidance via
    feedforward and feedback, creating
    expectation and comparing expectation with
    experienced outcome
  • They also yield motivated cognition as well as
    action tendencies
  • They all permit attunement to situations,
    possibilities, needs, and values, i.e., to
    reasons to think, feel, and do.

39
(No Transcript)
40
Kant on choice and liking
  • Every determination of choice proceeds from the
    representation of a possible action to the deed
    through the feeling of pleasure or displeasure,
    taking an interest in the action or its effect.
    MM, 6399

41
(No Transcript)
42
An example Kant on the good, the will, and
liking
  • despite all difference between the agreeable
    and the good, they do agree in this they are
    always connected with an interest in their
    object. This holds not only for the agreeable
    but also for what is good absolutely and in every
    respect, i.e., the moral good . For the good
    is the object of the will (a power of desire)
    determined by reason. But to will something and
    to have a liking for its existence, i.e., to take
    an interest in it, are identical. CJ 209

43
This is how Kant explained the possibility of
action from duty
  • Any consciousness of obligation depends upon
    moral feeling to make us aware of the constraint
    present in the thought of duty, there can be no
    duty to have the moral feeling or to acquire it
    . MM, 6399-400
  • Respect (reverentia) is, again, something
    subjective, a feeling of a special kind, not a
    judgment about an object that it would be a duty
    to bring about or promote. For, such a duty,
    regarded as a duty, could be represented to us
    only through the respect we have for it. A duty
    to have respect would thus amount to being put
    under obligations to duties. MM, 6402-403

44
Aristotle on acting for reasons
  • Now the origin of action (the efficient, not the
    final cause) is choice, and the origin of choice
    is appetition and purposive reasoning. An
    action is an end in itself and the object of
    appetition. Hence choice is either appetitive
    intellect or intellectual appetition and man is
    a principle of this kind. NE 1139a32-b5

45
Aristotle on action as practical attunement
  • Brutes have sensation, but no share in action.
    Pursuit and avoidance in the sphere of
    appetition correspond exactly to affirmation and
    negation in the sphere of intellect .
  • Since choice is deliberative appetition, it
    follows that if the choice is a good one, both
    the reasoning must be true and the desire right
    and the desire must pursue the same things that
    the reasoning asserts.
  • We are here speaking of intellect and truth in a
    practical sense the function of practical
    intellect is to arrive at the truth that
    corresponds to right appetition. NE
    1113a20-28

46
Rethinking the debate over internal and external
reasons?
  • We should reject the neo-Humean account of belief
    and desire
  • Attributing moral action the belief-desire
    model does not destroy the notion of acting for
    the right reason, with the right feeling, in the
    right way, at the right time
  • At the same time, attributing moral action to
    desire does not require any additional
    motivational state over respect for the moral
    law. It does not require external reasons.
  • Restricting reasons to what is derivable from
    someones existing subjective motivational set
    ignores the possibility that she might acquire
    new desires rationally, including respect for
    others, or for fairness, or for the moral law.

47
  • To Plotinus what we seek is VISION, what
  • wakes when we wake to desire
  • as the eye to the sun
  • It is just as if you should fall in love with one
    of the sparrows which fly by
  • when we wake to desire
  • - Frank Bidart, Desire
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com