Title: Uncertainty and Public Policy
1Uncertainty and Public Policy
- Expected Value and Expected Utility
- Risk-control and risk-shifting mechanisms
- Alternative models of individual behaviour under
uncertainty - Moral hazard and medical care
- (chap 7)
2Uncertainty and Public Policy
- Most choices are made under uncertainty as to the
possible outcomes these choices are essentially
gambles - The WTP for a risky commodity depends on the
likelihood of possible outcomes, as perceived by
the consumer. - How do individuals respond to changes in these
perceived probabilities? - How can public policies affect these perceptions?
3Uncertainty and Public Policy
- Objective to assess the economic costs of
uncertainty and the benefits of its reduction - Alternative models of individual behaviour under
uncertainty - The expected utility theorem individuals
mazimize expected utility. - Theory of games against persons the Slumlords
Dilemma (a prisonners dilemma) - Bounded Rationality
4States of the World
- Set of alternative states of the world the
different and mutually exclusive outcomes that
may result from the process generating the
uncertainty - Examples
- Fliping a coin 2 states, heads or tails
- Throwing a die six possible outcomes may arise
- Notice that the definition of the relevant states
of the world depends on the game that is being
played for a student, in this course it may be
Pass or Fail, while for another may be 18, 17,
16, less than 15, and for another, 10, 11, 12,
13, 14, more than 15...
5Expected Value
- Payoff of each state of the world, Xi
- Expected value of a risky situation the sum of
the payoff in each possible situation weighted by
the probability that it will occur - Suppose that there are N possible states, each
with a payoff Xi and a probability of occurring
of Pi, the expected value is,
6Expected Value
- If all the possible states are considered it must
always be true that - Consider the following three different games
- Game 1 A coin is flipped. If heads turn out,
you win (the payoff is) 100 and if tails appear,
the payoff is -0,5. - Game 2 if heads, you win 200 if tails, you lose
100 - Game 3 If heads, you win 20,000 if tails, you
lose 10,000 the losses may be paid in small
amounts spread over 30 years
7Expected Value
- Everybody would like to play game 1, many people
(although less) would play game 2 and very few
people would play game 3. Yet - EV1(1/2)100 (1/2)(-0.5)49.75
- EV2(1/2)200 (1/2)(-100)50
- EV3(1/2)20000 (1/2)(-10000)5000
- Having a positive or a large expected value is
not sufficient to make a game attractive in
addition to the expected value, most people also
consider how they feel about each possible outcome
8Expected Value
- A fair game is a game whose entry price equals
its EV. An entry price of 50 makes game 2 a fair
game, EV20 - Risk-averse people are those who choose not to
play fair games - Bernoulli explained this pattern people value
not the expected monetary outcome, but the
expected utility (its moral value). If utility
functions have decreasing marginal utility of
income, an expected gain of amount X is less
valued than an equal loss of the same amount. - We consider that the sole relevant outcome of a
gamble is the level of wealth to wich it
corresponds
9Expected Utility
- The formal economic theory of choice, formulated
by Von Neumann, and Oskar Morgenstern, assumes
the existence of a utility function U that
assigns numerical values with the satisfaction
associated with different outcomes. - The expected utility is the sum of the utility
associated with each possible state of the world,
weighted by the probability that it will occur
is the expected value of utility over all
possible outcomes - The Expected Utility Theorem, states that the
individual chooses among alternatives in order to
maximize expected utility
12th S, Oct 25
10Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- Suppose there are n possible outcomes, where X1
is the least preferred and Xn the most preferred.
Now assign arbitrary utility numbers to these two
extreme results, for instance U(X1)0, U(Xn )1 - Given these two values, we can assign utility
levels to the other possible outcomes - Start with Xi. Ask the individual to state the
probability pi that would make him indifferent
between Xi with certainty and playing a game with
probability pi of getting Xn and probability 1-
pi of obtaining X1. (There should exist a
sufficiently atractive game to make the
individual accept to play it. The higher Xi, the
higher must be pi for the individual to accept
it)
11Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- This probability, pi, represents how desirable
outcome Xi is the von Neumann - Morgenstern
technique consists in defining the utility of Xi
as the expected utility of the game that the
individual considers equally desirable to Xi - U(Xi) pi U(Xn)(1- pi )U(X1) or
- U(Xi) pi 10 pi
- The utility number of any outcome is the
probability of winning the top prize in a game
that the individual considers equivalent to that
outcome - Now, p10 and pn 1
- A rational individual will choose among gambles
based on their expected utilities, ie, on the
expected values of these Von-Neumann Morgenstern
utility index numbers
12Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- Example a game has only 2 possible outcomes
winning 50 or 0. Consider that the Utility of
winning 50 with certainty is 1 and the utility of
winning 0 with certainty is zero. Consider now
the outcome 10 with certainty. Its utility must
be less than 1 and larger than 0.
And there must (?) exist a lottery, with a
probability of wining between 0 and 1 that this
consumer considers indifferent to 10 with
certainty . Suppose it is 0.4
Utility
1
A
0.4
0
10
Wealth
50
13Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- The vertical axis shows the probability of
winning 50 necessary to make the individual
indifferent between playing that game and getting
the wealth on the horizontal axis with certainty
utility index of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
A
Utility
1
0.4
0
10
Wealth
50
14Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- Ray OA shows, for each possible probability, the
expected utility (on the vertical axis), and the
expected value of the lottery (on the horizontal
axis). In this case the expected value of the
lottery with a 0.4 chance of winning 50 is
E(V)0.4500.6020.
The expected utility of the lottery is
E(U)0.4U(50)0.6U(0) 0.4100.4
Utility
A
1
U(W)
0.4
C
0
10
20
Wealth
50
15Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- Risk-lovers are individuals who prefer to accept
fair games, (utility function is convex) and risk
neutrals are indifferent to fair games - Certain-wealth equivalent is the amount of
certain wealth that gives the individual the same
utility he has under the risky situation 10
- Pure risk cost the difference between the
expected wealth of a risky situation and its
certain equivalent 20-10
Utility
A
1
0.8
D
0.4
C
0
50
10
20
40
Wealth
16Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- The lottery indifferent to a certain-equivalent
wealth of 10 is having a proabability of wining
(50) of 0.4. And the expected value of that game
is 20 - Point C represents the expected value and the
expected utility from the gamble 0.4. Gambles
with higher (lower) probabilities of winning have
expected values and expected utilities on the ray
to the right (left) of C
Utility
1
A
0.4
C
0
10
50
20
Wealth
17Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- The utility index ranks risky situations
- consider 20 with certainty the individual is in
point D. Now propose the individual to play the
fair game consisting of winning 50 with
probability p0.4 at a price of 20 (the expected
value of the game).
The expected utility of the gamble is less than
the utility of the certain 20 the individual
will not play this fair game he is risk-averse
Utility
A
1
D
0.4
C
0
20
10
Wealth
50
18Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- Consider the game that gives 50 with probability
p0.8 and has entry price of 20. Its expected
value is 40. Its expected utility, 0.8, is larger
than the utility at D This risk-averse person
will accept to play it
Risk aversion is due to the concavity of the
utility function. Its slope is decreasing,
meaning that the marginal utility of income is
decreasing
Utility
A
1
0.8
D
0.4
C
0
20
40
10
Wealth
50
19Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- Risk-averse persons will pay to reduce risk this
is the reason for the existence of insurance - Consider that W050, and the probability of being
stolen is 0.6 (X1stolen0, Xn, not stolen50). C
is now the expected value of this situation. The
certain wealth equivalent is 10 for individual
red, 14 for individual green
Utility
A
1
D
0.4
C
0
10
20
40
14
Wealth
50
20Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- The individual with the green Utility function
will pay up to 30636 (the expected loss plus
the pure risk cost) to get a full-coverage
insurance against theft. His net wealth, after
paying this insurance, would be 50-3614, whether
he is stolen or not. The other will pay up to 40
to avoid the risk
Utility
A
1
D
0.4
C
0
40
10
Wealth
50
20
14
21Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- How does the amount of risk affect this
individuals choice? Suppose that W050, but only
40 are at a risk of being stolen. The probability
of being stolen is 0.6 again. The individual will
be at point B (if stolen) or A (if not stolen).
The straight line BA represents now the possible
combinations of expected wealth and expected
utility.
Utility
The risk is lower now
A
1
D
B
0.4
C
0
10
Wealth
50
20
22Utility function of von-Neumann-Morgenstern
- The gamble is smaller. Then
- For any expected wealth, the espected utility of
a smaller gamble is higher - For any expected wealth, a smaller gamble has a
lower pure risk cost
Example p of theft 0.75 EV0.25500.751020 EU
0.25U(50)0.75U(10) .55gt 0.4 Lower stakes
give higher utility
Utility
A
1
D
K
0.55
0.4
C
0
10
Wealth
50
20
23Measures of risk
- The pure risk cost depends on the individuals
preferences - There are several measures that do not depend on
preferences, like the variance and the
standard-deviation of the outcomes - Variance is
- it can be shown that the pure risk is
aproximately proportional to the variance - A general rule of thumb is that there is
aproximately 90 of chances that the actual
outcome will lie within 2 Standard-Deviations of
the expected value
24Risk-aversion and gambling
- Empirically, risk-averse behaviour is
predominant everybody diversifies portfolios,
and buys insurance at larger than fair prices. - Basic risk aversion may be compatible with a
risk-lover behaviour for other ranges of wealth
25
58
50
48
25Risk-control and risk-shifting mechanisms
- Risk-pooling a group of individuals facing
independent risks agree to share any losses (or
gains) among them - Ex n2, W0 50, and 5 has a p .2 of being
stolen. For each individual there are only two
possible outcomes, 50 with p .8 and 45 with p
.2 gt EV 49 - Suppose they agree to pool their risks.
Possibilities are - 1. Neither is robbed W50, p .8(.8).64gt32
- 2. They are both subject to theft, W45, p
.2(.2).04gt1,8 - 3. One is robbed and the other is not, W47.5, p
.32gt15,2 - EV49 again, but the probability of ending up
close to it is larger the risk has been reduced -
26Risk-pooling
- When the number of individuals joining the
agreement increases, the risk costs decrease.
This is the logic of insurance, where insurance
companies bear the transaction costs of
organizing the pool, keeping information about
damages and making the required transfers. When
these transaction costs are large relative to
expected losses, people should self-insure - Risk pooling also explains why firms in unrelated
business merge to become conglomerates, or why
people diverfy their portfolio -
27Risk-spreading
- Risk-spreading occurs when individuals share the
returns of one risky situation - Examples diversification of firm ownership on
the stock market - The proof that risk spreading reduces risk is
that it must decrease the variance, which is, in
turn, proportional to the risk cost. Xi is the
ith outcome of the risky investment
28Risk-spreading
- Other institutions that facilitate risk-spreading
are futures markets in these markets, the
supplier sells part of its future production at a
price specified now certainty of income is
achieved - Im may happen that the total amount of risk in
not exogenously given. Instead, total risk (or
risk creating activities) may increase due to
risk-cost reducing mechanisms
29 Social mechanisms designed to reduce the costs
of risk
- Social mechanisms aimed at decreasing or shifting
risk-costs - Limited liability (risk-shifting)
- Disaster insurance
- Quality certification like occupational licensing
requirements the decrease in uncertainty is
accompanied by entry restrictions that create
market power (M. Friedman and K. Arrow) - Consumer product safety restrictions
- Health standards on workplace
- Medical care insurance moral hazard and the
increasing costs of medical insurance systems
30Alternative models of behaviour under
uncertainty game theory
- When uncertainty concerns people behaviour,
instead of states of nature, game theory helps. - Strategic games and the prisonners dilemma the
dominant strategy is for each party not to
cooperate. - Applications
- adjacent buildings in a slum. The solution must
be the internalization of benefits and costs - world free trade and GATT
- The extreme risk-averter and the maximin strategy
31Alternative models of behaviour under
uncertainty bounded rationality
- There are limits to human rationality. In face of
excessively complex games people develop
satisficing (and not optimizing) routines - Empirical evidence (disaster insurance in
earthquake areas) suggests that in some
circumstances compulsory insurance may be
required - Thaler suggested that two particular kinds of
bounded rationality are frequent loss aversion
and myopia - Loss aversion. People weight more heavily losses
than gaind - Myopia people frame long run decisions in terms
of their short-term consequences
32Alternative models of behaviour under
uncertainty bounded rationality
- Kahneman and Tversky found that people (i) weight
gains and losses separately and then add their
separate values and (ii) attach more importance
to losses than to gains. - Suppose that at a moment, you are confronted with
an unexpected gain of 100 and an unexpected loss
of 80. Overall, wealth increases by 20. However,
utility may decrease - Their hypothesis is that people evaluate
alternatives with a value function, defined over
changes of wealth, and not with a conventional
utility function
33Alternative models of behaviour under
uncertainty bounded rationality
- Conventional utility function
- The Kahneman-Tversky Value function
V(100)
-80
100
V(-80)
W0
W020
34Alternative models of behaviour under
uncertainty bounded rationality
- Consequences of the Value function the framing
effect. According with the value function
hypothesis, one should - Segregate gains decomposing a large gain into
smaller ones increases utility - Combine losses two separate losses cause less
pain if combined together in a single, larger one - Combine small losses with a larger gain
- Segregate small gains from large losses a loss
of 200 accompanied by a gain of 25 is better for
most people than a loss of 175 (silver-lining
effect)
35Alternative models of behaviour under
uncertainty bounded rationality
- The equity premium puzzle the allocation of
portfolio between stocks and bonds, (with a
difference in their long-run average rate of
return of 5-6 percent) can only be an equilibrium
with an implausibly high risk-aversion. The
hypothesis of bounded rationality can help
explain this puzzle. - More information may increase myopia
- If human behaviour is characterized by myopia and
loss aversion, this must be taken into account on
the discussion of (i) policies concerning
individual control of retirement accounts and
(ii) activities with negative environmental
effects
36Moral hazard and medical insurance
- Medical insurance is (partyly) responsible for
the dramatic increase in the costs of medical
care that has occurred worldwide. - Medical insurance reduces the cost of risk,
through risk-shifting and risk-pooling. However,
the insurance changes the economic incentives
faced by individuals and hence their behaviour - Medical expenses are not random effects they
depend on the occurrence of a random effect (the
illness), but also on the consumers (and his
doctors) preferences, incomes and on the prices
of the services. And insurance changes these
prices.
37Moral hazard
- Moral hazard problems arise when in a deal one of
the parties has incentives to undertake a hidden
action (impossible to monitor) that harms the
other contractor. - It requires that there is an information
asymmetry between the two parties envolved in the
deal, and that this asymetry concerns the hidden
action, (an action taken by one of the
contractors after the deal and which affects the
outcome (but not completely determines it) - In a principal-agent relationship with hidden
action there is always a moral hazard problem - In the health-insurance problem the principal is
the company and the agent is the insured. The
hidden action is the excessive consumption of
medical services if ill
38Moral hazard and medical insurance
- With full-coverage insurance, there is no cost
control of the medical care industry. - In fact, full coverage private insurance can be
offered only if demand in inelastic. - Example 2 states, ill or healthy with pi0.5.
If uninsured the individual will buy 50 units at
a price 1 if illness occurs. The expected cost is
25, and every body would purchase an insurance at
this premium.
Demand
1
50
Quantity of medical services
39Moral hazard and medical insurance
- With a full-coverage insurance, and elastic
demand EAG the individual will buy 100. The cost
for the insurance company is now 0.510050 and
it will offer the insurance at this price - The benefit to the individual is 25 as before and
hence he may not buy the insurance - we have a prisonners dilemma everybody would be
better if restraining from excessive consumption
but no one will do it by himself.
Demand
E
A
1
G
50
100
Quantity of medical services
40Medical insurance with deductibles
- This problem may also affect actions that might
prevent the illness - Deductibles and coinsurance may help decrease the
moral hazard problem in health insurance - Suppose there is a deductible for the first 60
units. Then the individual has 2 options - A not file a claim and pay 50
- B file a claim, pay 60 and consume 100
- This person chooses B
Demand
E
A
1
G
50
Quantity of medical services
41Medical insurance and deductibles
- If there is a demand curve for insurance for each
illness, the existence of the fixed deductible
leads people to file claims in the presence of
serious diseases and not for less severe problems
Demand
E
A
1
G
50
Quantity of medical services
42Medical insurance and coinsurance
- Suppose t0.1 the individual will purchase less
than before, which means that the insurance will
be less costly. The lower the elasticity, the
lower will be the restrain in consumption - Coinsurance partially shifts the risk it shifts
the more expensive units, ie, prevents the
losses where the marginal utility of wealth is
gratest and decreases the consumption of the
least-valued units
Demand
E
A
1
G
50
Quantity of medical services
43Insurance and adverse selection
- Another relevant informational asymmetry is
adverse selection it occurs when different
individuals have different probabilities of
having unfavourable outcomes. If insurance
providers do not have accurate measures of
expected loss, they will not be able to set
equilibrium premiums and the insurance market
will not function properly - The market for lemons
- Signaling if the low-risk individuals could
signal that, they would benefit. Signals, to be
informative, must be difficult to fake (Sports
car vs a peugeot 404)
44Designing national health-care systems
- Usually, deductibles and coinsurance are income
contigent - How can the social cost be measured? Usually the
market price conveys the information about the
amount of resources given up by society in order
to supply one further unit. But in this sector
entry restrictions may make the market price
higher than the social cost. If so, the optimal
quantity of medical services will be larger than
the one uninsured people would choose.
45Designing national health-care systems
- What about measuring benefits?
- People seek health, not medical service, and the
relation between the 2 is not well known
(disagreement among doctors is common) - The physician is supposed to be the patients
agent, but in a fee-for-service system is also
the seller of the services. There is an obvious
conflict of interest. A solution is managed care
systems, whereby suppliers have incentives to
save. Other is hospital charges determined in
accordance with a schedule of diagnostic related
groups. Still another is a national health service