Normative Guidance and Moral Motivation - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

1 / 35
About This Presentation
Title:

Normative Guidance and Moral Motivation

Description:

How we talk, eat, stand, move, work, cooperate, compete, play, grieve, express ... from iustus (justice); originally from yewes (law; similar: jury, abjure, injury) ... – PowerPoint PPT presentation

Number of Views:34
Avg rating:3.0/5.0
Slides: 36
Provided by: lice230
Category:

less

Transcript and Presenter's Notes

Title: Normative Guidance and Moral Motivation


1
Normative Guidance and Moral Motivation
  • Peter Railton
  • Department of Philosophy
  • University of Michigan
  • Oslo, October 2008

2
Normative guidance
  • Normative guidance is pervasive
  • Morality, of course
  • What we believe
  • How we think
  • How we feel
  • What we want
  • How we talk, eat, stand, move, work, cooperate,
    compete, play, grieve, express affective, joke,
    give talks at conferences, build
  • We are in some sense made for normative
    guidance our psychology rapidly acquires norms
    and can be guided effectively by norms without
    direct supervision. This enables us to be guided
    by vastly more norms than we recognize.

3
Normative force
  • But what sort of psychology is this?
  • What is it to follow a norm, or find something
    normative? How is normative force operative
    within our psychology or any psychology?
  • I will argue a compound attitude of a special
    kind. It involves not one but two distinctive
    families of normative concepts.

4
Two families of normative concepts
  • (1) Normative concepts proper
  • Norm
  • Rule
  • Correct
  • Right/Wrong
  • Duty
  • Law
  • (2) Evaluative concepts proper
  • Good/Bad
  • Value
  • Worth
  • Virtue
  • Beauty

5
(1) Normative concepts proper
  • Norm from norma (carpenters square)
    originally from gno- (to know similar
    cognition, recognition, nomological, gnomon,
    abnormal)

6
Norma
7
The norma permits and enables
  • A priori guidance
  • A standard of correctness
  • Building rectilinearly
  • Cutting uniformly so that separate pieces match
  • Sharing tasks of building
  • Reproducing a model in arbitrary scale
  • Compare Wittgenstein on logic

8
Contour gauge
9
(No Transcript)
10
(1) Normative concepts proper, continued
  • Rule from regula (ruler) originally from reg-
    (to be straight, to move in a straight line
    similar direct, rectify, regulate, reign,
    royal, Reich, Recht, riki)

11
Regula
12
(1) Normative concepts proper, continued
  • Right also from reg-
  • Wrong from Scandanavian originally from wer-
    (to bend or turn similar divert, invert,
    pervert, version)
  • Correct from co (with) reg- (straight)

13
(1) Normative concepts proper, continued
  • Just from iustus (justice) originally from
    yewes (law similar jury, abjure, injury)
  • Law from Old Norse lagu (that which is laid
    down) originally from legh- (to lie, to lay
    similar ledger, belay, fellow, coverlet)

14
(1) Normative concepts proper, continued
  • Duty from devoir (must), originally from ghabh-
    (to give or receive similar debt, gift, able)
  • Obligation from ob- (inverse) ligare (to
    bind), originally from leig- (to bind similar
    ligament, religion)

15
An example of normative force?Obligation and
the power of the gift
  • Marcel Mauss (1872-1950), The Gift "What power
    resides in the object given that causes its
    recipient to pay it back?"
  • Gifts are not free, but a form of reciprocal
    exchange
  • In return for the gift is an obligation to the
    giver
  • Therefore, a social bond is created, with a norm
    of giving due return
  • The gift therefore bears a symbolic power, that
    remains tied to the giver and that binds the
    receiver
  • This is a social fact, a norm transcending the
    individual exchange

16
Normativity and norms
  • This sort of explanation traces normative force
    back to norms, to the idea of conforming to a
    standard correctness and incorrectness.
  • But What gives us the norm? Why is conformity
    to this standard normative?
  • In many cases, the answer seems to be obvious
  • The custom of gift-giving
  • The standards of a practice or profession
  • Religious and secular laws
  • Social norms or codes
  • Languages
  • Rules of logic
  • Agreements and conventions
  • Individual principles or resolutions

17
Why or when is a standard normative?
  • Positive theory of law A law is a command
    backed by force
  • This cannot be the concept of a law. Many
    commands are given between individuals, backed by
    force or threat of force. (Rousseaus highway
    robber.)
  • To be law, there must be some recognition or
    standing as law the command must be issued by an
    appropriate authority. This is already a
    normative concept. (Hart.)
  • Handbook of Sociology A norm is a rule backed
    by social sanction
  • The notion of a sanction (as opposed to a mere
    infliction of harm upon oneself or others),
    already is a normative concept.

18
Normative regress
  • Meta-rule A norm can be given force by a
    meta-rule that requires it.
  • This simply launches a regress. It cannot be
    norms all the way down. (Compare Wittgenstein
    on rule-following.)
  • Could norms be self-requiring? There are too
    many norms and meta-norms norms of language,
    norms of politeness, norms of prudence, norms of
    morality, etc. A proliferation of requirements
    and standards that cannot all be met.

19
Normativity without norms?
  • Must there therefore be some forms of normativity
    that do not presuppose a standard or take the
    form of a rule? They might support or justify a
    standard or rule to supply an answer to the
    question Why follow this rule rather than that
    one? but not on the basis of yet another
    standard or requirement.
  • A norma or regula tells us how to build
    rectilinearly, but not whether this is a good
    idea, whether we want this, whether this would be
    desirable or beautiful, what good or harm it
    might bring, etc. It does not give us the
    concepts to discuss this.

20
(2) Evaluative concepts proper
  • Value from valoir (to be strong, to be worth),
    originally from wal- (to be strong similar
    valid, valor, prevail, equivalent, valence)
  • Good from Middle English, originally from
    ghedh- (to unite or join, to fit similar
    together, gather)
  • Virtue from virtus (manliness, excellence)
    originally from wi-ro (man similar virile,
    world, werewolf)
  • True from trewe (firm, trustworthy) originally
    from deru- (to be firm, solid similar tree,
    trust, endure, truce, Druid)
  • Beauty from deu- (to do, to favor or revere
    similar benefit, benefaction, beatitude,
    dynasty)

21
Two families of normative concepts
  • (1) Normative vocabulary proper
  • Rule, norm, standard, law, regulate, correct,
    rectified, required, permitted
  • fit conforms to rule or standard, satisfies
    condition
  • Voluntary ought implies can compliance can be
    required (Kant observantia)
  • Formal one can operate correctly in full
    conformity to the guidance or requirements of
    this domain without endorsing conclusions form,
    rite, ritual, contract normative detachment
    not guaranteed
  • (2) Evaluative vocabulary proper
  • Good, valuable, true, credible,
    desirable, beautiful, important
  • fit appropriateness, suitability, intrinsically
    compelling, endorsed, appreciated, admired (Kant
    reverentia)
  • Non-voluntary the credible yields confidence
    the evident convinces the compelling wins over
    or impresses the good and the beautiful attract
    the desirable seduces
  • Substantive one cannot operate in this domain
    responding fully appropriately to its guidance
    without endorsing, appreciating, or aiming for
    the conclusions support normative detachment
    accept, endorse, commit, believe, seek, love

22
Mental acts and attitudes
  • Normative concepts proper are applicable to
    mental acts that are more or less voluntary
  • Reasoning
  • Calculating
  • Deciding
  • Obeying or complying
  • Evaluative concepts proper are applicable to
    involuntary attitudes as well as acts
  • Believing
  • Desiring
  • Valuing
  • Admiring

23
Affect and emotion
  • Discussions of normativity tend to emphasize two
    dimensions of the agents psychology cognition
    and motivation.
  • For some, the puzzle about normativity is how an
    attitude could be both cognitive and motivating
    (the problem of internalism for normative
    judgments).
  • Note that an agent equipped with cognition and
    motivation alone is in principle capable of
    compliance with norms or rules meeting
    normative requirements.
  • For the evaluative, however, emotion or affect,
    the third sphere of psychology, comes into play
    trust, confidence, admiration, appreciation,
    affection, disgust, enjoyment

24
Affect and emotion, continued
  • The involvement of affect permits the evaluative
    to play a role in the psyche complementary to
    rules and prior, completing the picture of
    normative guidance.
  • The affective revolution in psychology dual
    processes express and implicit.
  • The implicit is faster than the explicit, shapes
    or colors it, and is mediated pervasively by
    affect.
  • This intuitive psychology is sometimes
    contrasted with normative psychology. But it
    also is part of normative psychology.

25
Normative guidance from the inside out
  • What is it to be normatively guided?
  • Explicitly or actively, e.g., to take something
    as normative or accord it authority?
  • Implicitly or passively, e.g. to have ones
    thoughts, feelings, and actions shaped by norms,
    to experience a rule as normative?
  • Two elements appear to be essential in both
    cases
  • Attitude norm
  • E.g. trust rule
  • respect law
  • accept custom
  • admire role or model

26
Explaining normative guidance requires concepts
from both families
  • Epistemology Rule of probability or logic
    doesnt govern ones inferences unless one
    trusts or has confidence in the rule.
  • Belief itself reflects this belief that p
    degree of confidence that p
  • Prudence Rule of promoting long-term well-being
    doesnt govern behavior unless one cares or has
    self-concern.
  • Desire itself reflects this desire that p
    degree of preference that p
  • Social practice Rule of conduct doesnt
    govern behavior normatively from the inside out
    unless it is internalized, accepted, deferred to,
    identified with.

27
A simple model of normative guidance
  • Let us say that agent As conduct is in the
    relevant sense guided by norm N only if
  • Agent A is disposed to act in a way conducive to
    compliance with N such that some representation
    of N plays a regulative role in As C-ing, where
    this involves
  • - some disposition on As part to notice
    failures to comply with N
  • some disposition on As part to experience
    discomfort when this occurs and to exert effort
    to establish conformity with N even when the
    departure from N is subject to no external
    punishment and has no further effects of its own.
  • E.g., infants over-regularization of English.

28
Normative guidance, beyond custom and acceptance
  • For mere custom or ritual, internalization of
    the sort indicated above may suffice.
  • This is just how we do things.
  • An agent, however, could experience such
    normative guidance as alien or recalcitrant
    e.g., discomfort with behavior the agent no
    longer deems inappropriate. (Experiments on
    compliance.)
  • We seem to need a stronger connection between the
    agent and the norm in order to understand the
    normative force of morality and possibility of
    moral motivation.
  • Durkheim on religion devoir vouloir and vouloir
    devoir

29
Normative endorsement
  • Understanding morality seems to require more than
    internalizationattitude of accepting,
    identifying with, or endorsing a norm. This can
    be latent. Some of its marks
  • Freely avow and defend N
  • Treat N as non-optional, non-hypothetical
  • Treat N as objective rather than merely
    subjective reify
  • See disagreement with N as error
  • See judgment relative to N as placing a demand
    upon all others
  • See sanctioning attitude or punishment for
    violation of N as warranted, directed at self and
    at others

30
Some questions
  • Do we find societies where no norms show these
    marks?
  • This is hard to imagine. Consider
  • Norms of authority regarding what to believe
  • Norms of fairness in exchange
  • Norms concerning gender or family roles
  • Norms concerning in-group and out-group
  • Norms of social hierarchy

31
Our morality
  • Consider morality in the sense most familiar to
    us not a descriptive or anthropological notion,
    but the idea of what system of norms really is
    authoritative for us. What we endorse.
  • This seems to embody at least the following
    elements of a moral point of view
  • Rational
  • Impartial
  • Universal
  • Benevolent
  • Binding
  • This sort of scope is unprecedented in the
    environment of early human adaptation.
  • We would need to leverage and redeploy our
    inherited moral psychology.

32
Antecedents
  • On the other hand, we have ample testimony to
    this sort of normative ambition in the
    monotheistic religions that prevail in much of
    the world. Clearly there is a normative
    aspiration to universality that finds a strong
    root in human nature.
  • Humean ingredients
  • Self-interest
  • Limited generosity
  • Empathy
  • Capacity for rule-following
  • Planfulness
  • Kantian ingredients
  • Reciprocity
  • Reflection
  • Generalization

33
Moral motivation
  • Cobbling these together, we can motivation on
    behalf of a moral point of view
  • That would be a social and cultural achievement,
    using evolved psychic capacities that may fight
    with other evolved sentiments.
  • We should expect moral intuitions to fit only
    approximately.
  • No different in principle from theoretical reason
    or language. Build refined tools with simple
    tools.

34
Normative force and normative freedom
  • To have the sort of authority we attribute to it,
    morality must be more than a set of normative
    requirements we happen to have internalized, a
    sense of devoir vouloir.
  • It must also be an expression of our normative
    freedom, our evaluative aspiration to be able to
    see and understand ourselves and one another in
    terms free of all coercion, parochialism, and
    mystification.
  • This is the vouloir devoir of our
    self-representation as moral beings. It could be
    hubris.

35
Vindicating vs. debunking
  • Can we see ourselves without illusion and still
    have this sense of ourselves as moral beings?
  • The reflection test
  • Debunking stories Nietzsche, Freud?
  • Vindicating stories Hume, Darwin?
Write a Comment
User Comments (0)
About PowerShow.com